Главная · Поиск книг · Поступления книг · Top 40 · Форумы · Ссылки · Читатели

Настройка текста
Перенос строк


    Прохождения игр    
Demon's Souls |#14| Flamelurker
Demon's Souls |#13| Storm King
Demon's Souls |#12| Old Monk & Old Hero
Demon's Souls |#11| Мaneater part 2

Другие игры...


liveinternet.ru: показано число просмотров за 24 часа, посетителей за 24 часа и за сегодня
Rambler's Top100
Справочники - Различные авторы Весь текст 5859.38 Kb

Project Gutenberg's Encyclopedia, vol. 1 ( A - Andropha

Предыдущая страница Следующая страница
1 ... 204 205 206 207 208 209 210  211 212 213 214 215 216 217 ... 500
that these records are wont to contain reflexions which, though 
wanting in scientific precision, can be utilized by science. 

Psychological analysis of material. 

We now come to the work of scientific construction proper.  
The finer analysis of the objects which please aesthetically 
as well as of the agreeable type of consciousness to which 
they minister belongs to the psychologist, and it is noteworthy 
that the best recent contributions to the science have been 
made by men who were either known as psychologists or at least 
had trained themselves in psychological analysis.  A word or 
two must suffice to indicate the more important directions 
of the theoretic interpretation.  We may in illustrating this 
set out from the convenient triple division of the factors in 
aesthetic experience: (A) the sensuous, (B) the perceptual or 
formal, (C) the imaginative, including all that is suggested 
by the aesthetic presentation, its meaning and expressiveness. 

The sensuous factor.  Physiological aesthetics. 

(A) In dealing with the sensuous factor the psychologist is 
materially aided by the physiologist.  It is sufficient to 
point to the contribution made to the analysis of musical 
sensations by the classical researches of Helmholtz (see 
below).  Yet the application of a knowledge of physiological 
conditions seems as yet to be of little service when we 
come to the finer aspects of this sensuous experience, 
to the subtle effects of colour combination, for example, 
and to the nuances of feeling-tone attaching to different 
tints.  In the finer analysis of the sensuous material of 
aesthetic enjoyment it is the psychologist who counts.22 

Psychological problems. 

Among the valuable contributions recently made in this domain 
one may instance the careful determination of the aesthetically 
important characteristics of the sensations of sight and hearing, 
such as the finely graduated variety of their qualities (colour 
and tone), their capability of entering into combinations 
in which they preserve their individuality, including the 
important combinations of time and space form.  With these 
are to be included the distinguishing characteristics of the 
concomitant feeling-tones, e.g. their comparative calmness 
and their clear separation from the sensations which they 
accompany.  These characteristics help us to understand 
the greater refinement of these senses and also the more 
prolonged as well as varying enjoyment which they contribute, 
as well as the extension of this enjoyment by imaginative 
reproduction.23 Next to this determination of important 
aesthetic characteristics of the two senses may be named a 
finer probing of the nuances of pleasurable tone exhibited by 
the several colours and tones.  A point still needing special 
investigation is extent of the sensuous factor in aesthetic 
enjoyment.  There has been a tendency in aesthetic theory 
to over-intellectualize aesthetic experience and to find 
the value even of the sensuous factor in some intellectual 
principle, as when it is said (by Plato and Hegel among 
others) that a smooth or level tone and a uniform mass of 
colour owe their value to the principle of unity.  But such 
prolongation (within obvious limits) in time or space is a 
condition of the full enjoyment of the distinctive quality 
of an individual tone or colour, and as such has a sensuous 
value.  Aesthetics has to prove the sensuous value, the 
pleasure which is due not only to the feeling-tones of the 
several sensations but to those of their variods combinations.  
Spite of a tendency of late to disparage the co-operation of 
the ``motor sensations'' connected with movements of the eye 
in the aesthetic appreciation of linear form, e.g. curves, 
evidence suggests that certain curves, like fine gradations 
of colour, may owe a considerable part of their value to 
a mode of varying the sensuous experience which is in a 
peculiar manner agreeable.  On the other hand, this theoretic 
investigation of sense-material will need to determine with 
care the added value due to the action of experience in giving 
something of meaning to particular colours and tones and 
their combinations, e.g. warmth of colour, height of tone. 

The perceptual factor. 

(B) Under the scientific treatment of the perceptual or 
formal factor in aesthetic experience we have many special 
problems, of which only a few can be touched on here.  Taking 
this factor to include all combinations of elements in which 
there is a more or less distinct perception of pleasing 
relations, we meet here with such work as that of C. Stumpf 
(Ton-psychologie) in determining the way in which tones 
combine and tend to fuse.  Later experiments have added to our 
knowledge of the obscure subject of colour harmony, enabhng 
us to distinguish pleasing contrasts of colour from the more 
restful combinations of nearly allied tints.  Our knowledge 
of pleasing form in the narrower sense, that is to say, 
space and time form, has been advanced by a number of recent 
inquiries.  The value of symmetry, the meaning of proportion 
and the aesthetic value to be set on certain proportions, 
the forms of these are some of the points dealt with in more 
central and in special works24.  In the case of forms, 
still more than in that of sensuous elements, it is needful to 
determine the extent to which the value of the formal aspect 
is modified by experience and the acquisition of meaning.  
This is pretty certainly the source of the aesthetic value 
claimed for certain proportions, whether in the human figure 
or other organic forms or in the freer constructions of form 
in art.25 Another problem is to determine the influence of 
the feeling-tones of the combining elements on the pleasing 
character of the whole.  It is probable that a particular 
combination of colours owes something of its pleasure value 
to a harmony of the feeling-tones of the elements.  This 
is pretty certainly the case where the feeling-tones of the 
elements are closely akin, as in the case of a number of low 
tones of colours, or of architectural or other forms where 
one formal element--say, a vertical line, a rectangle of a 
certain proportion or a particular variety of arch--repeats 
itself and becomes a dominating feature of the whole. 

The imaginative factor. 

(C) The imaginative factor---which corresponds with what 
Fechner calls the ``indirect''---includes all that imaginative 
activity adds to our enjoyment when we contemplate an aesthetic 
object.  It may consist first of all in recalling concrete 
experiences firmly associated with the object, as when the 
sight of wild-flowers in a London street calls up an image 
of fields and lanes.  In order that these images may add to 
the aesthetic value of the object they must correspond to 
our common associations, as distinguished from accidental 
individual ones.  A large increase of aesthetic enjoyment 
comes to us through such suggested images.  Although in 
general it is images of concrete objects which are called 
up, ideas of a more abstract character may take part though 
they tend in this case to assume a concrete aspect.  This is 
illustrated in the appreciation of ``typical beauty'' in which 
a concrete form represents in an exceptional way the common 
form of a species, and in that of symbolic representation.  
An important part of this work of association is to render 
objects expressive of mental states, as when we read off the 
particular shade of feeling expressed by a natural scene.26 

Freer play of imagination. 

In the poetic contemplation of nature, her forces, her gladness 
and other moods, this imaginative activity, though still deriving 
leading to an investment of natural objects with a new and more 
fanciful meaning, as when we ``apperceive'' a willow drooping 
over a pond or the front of an old cottage under a quasi-human 
form, endowing it with something akin to our own feelings and 
memories.  What, it may be asked, is the whole range of this 
freer play of a life-giving fancy in our aesthetic enjoyment? 
Some recent theorists have attempted to answer this question 
by saying that it constitutes a vital element in all aesthetic 
contemplation.  Th. Lipps and others who follow him seek to 
show that this vitalizing activity of the fancy, which produces 
a new and illusory object, is the essential ingredient in 
the aesthetic enjoyment of the forms of material objects.  
According to this theory, when in the aesthetic mood I enjoy 
the form of a tree, of a church steeple or of the front of 
a Greek temple, I am not only ascribing life and feeling to 
it, but am projecting myself in fancy into the object thus 
constructed, feeling for the moment that I am the tree or the 
steeple.  The process of vivification is carried out as 
follows.  Lines represent certain movements, and in the 
aesthetic mood we translate all lines and so all forms back 
into the corresponding movements, which may be merely imagined 
(as Lipps himself thinks, or may be realized in part by 
sensuous elements, viz. motor sensations; which again may 
be regarded either as concomitants of eye movements, or as 
arising from an organically connected impulse to move the hand 
along the lines followed by the eye.27 Thus the columns of 
a temple represent upward movement, and are apperceived as 
striving upwards so as to resist the downward pressure of the 
entablature.  Since movements are the great means of expression 
in man, this imaginative reading of movement into motionless 
and even massive and stable forms enables us to endow them 
with quasi-human feelings.  In looking, for example, at 
the weighty masses of a building we enter sympathetically 
into the successful strivings of the supporting structures 
to resist the downward thrust of gravity in the supported 
masses.  The theory here briefly indicated28 is interesting 
as illustrating an attempt from the psychological side to find a 
scientific support for philosophic idealism or expressionalism.  
It is already beginning to be recognized in Germany as an 
exaggeration.  It may be enough to say that as applied to forms 
generally, including those of sculpture and architecture, the 
theory is opposed by our ordinary way of speaking, which implies 
quite another point of view in the aesthetic contemplation 
of form, namely, that of a spectator external to the object 
contemplated.  When our eye glides over the beauties of a 
statue, our imaginative activity so far from transporting us 
within the object carries us as tactual feelers outside the 
surface.  Similarly, when we delight in the divided spaces 
of a Gothic roof, so far from being imaginatively engaged in 
taking part in the efforts and strains of pillar, arch and 
the rest, we move in fancy along the pathways defined by the 
designer, tactually feeling and appreciating each dimension, 
each detail of form.  The attempt to force a theory fitted 
for poetry on sculpture and architecture would rob these of 
their distinctive aesthetic values; in the one case, of the 
plastic beauty of finely moulded marble surfaces as realized 
by imaginative excursions of the hand; and in the other 
case, of the perfect stillness and stability which give 
to great structures their solemn and quieting aspect.29 

Aesthetic Illusion. 

The theory of a vitalizing play of imagination (Einfuhlung) 
running through all modes of aesthetic contemplation is an 
exaggeration of the element of illusion which certainly characterizes 
this contemplation.  As suggested above, by blotting out for 
the moment the perception of all save that which pleases it 
substitutes a new for the more solid reality of our practical 
mood.  Moreover, as a state of perceptual absorption in which 
Предыдущая страница Следующая страница
1 ... 204 205 206 207 208 209 210  211 212 213 214 215 216 217 ... 500
Ваша оценка:
Комментарий:
  Подпись:
(Чтобы комментарии всегда подписывались Вашим именем, можете зарегистрироваться в Клубе читателей)
  Сайт:
 
Комментарии (2)

Реклама